Flash News

"जिबन पर्यन्त शिक्षाका लागि पुस्तकालय (Library for lifelong education)"

Thursday, October 9, 2025

Applied Ontology: An Introduction," edited by Katherine Munn and Barry Smith.

The following is a comprehensive book review of "Applied Ontology: An Introduction," edited by Katherine Munn and Barry Smith. This volume presents a powerful argument for the systematic application of philosophical ontology to the practical challenges of modern information management, particularly within the domains of medicine and biology.


An Overview of Themes, Arguments, and Structure

"Applied Ontology: An Introduction" is a collaborative volume that asserts the necessity of integrating rigorous philosophical methods, particularly those derived from ontology, into the development of automated information systems. The book's central argument is that current information systems (such as electronic databases, terminologies, and taxonomies) are often designed idiosyncratically, making them unable to share data (interoperable) or serve as reliable inputs for automated reasoning.

The volume introduces the core theme that ontology is the philosophical discipline which aims to understand how things in the world are divided into categories and how these categories are related together. The goal of the contributors is to show how philosophical insights can inform the creation of structured, automated representations, also called 'ontologies'.

The key arguments revolve around advocating for the realist orientation as an antidote to prevailing deficiencies. This orientation holds that sound knowledge representation must aim to represent the world itself, not merely convenient conceptualizations of it (a methodology critiqued as "pragmatist conceptualism"). The book emphasizes the doctrine of realist fallibilism, which combines a "healthy intellectual humility" with the conviction that humans can take measures to procure true beliefs about the world.

The book is organized into an introduction and thirteen chapters contributed by various philosophers and information scientists. The chapters systematically explore the theoretical foundation (formal ontology and realism), essential structural tools (granular partitions and classification theory), and deep ontological distinctions (continuants vs. occurrents, universals vs. particulars, and relational logic). Although the methods are intended to be broadly applicable, the book limits its focus primarily to the domains of biology and medicine.

Analysis of Style, Tone, and Perspective

The overall tone of "Applied Ontology" is urgent, expert, and reformative. The contributors stress the "urgency of applying rigorous philosophical methods" because doing so has "vast potential" for making information systems interoperable and efficient.

The perspective is consistently one of realist ontological perspectivalism, which argues that we can gain knowledge of reality via a multiplicity of veridical granular partitions. This stance is consciously pitted against conceptualism, a view widespread in information science where the definition of 'concept' is often loosely applied, leading to confusion about the representation target.

The writing style is designed to bridge the gap between abstract philosophy and practical engineering. Katherine Munn’s introduction is explicitly non-technical, using accessible metaphors, such as imagining a brilliant scientist scribbling a theory on a beer mat. However, the volume quickly moves toward rigorous, formalized treatments, including discussions of first-order logic (FOL) and description logics (DLs), making the style necessarily dense in later chapters. The clarity is enhanced by drawing on a deep tradition, particularly Aristotelian methodology concerning categories and hierarchical taxonomy, which is shown to have new relevance for modern bioinformatics.

Evaluation of Strengths and Weaknesses

Strengths: A major strength is the book’s unwavering commitment to foundational rigor. The authors provide crucial clarity on distinctions often blurred in information science, such as the difference between universals (kinds) and particulars (instances) or the critical difference between sets and classes.

The critique of existing biomedical terminologies (the "concept orientation") is a strong point, yielding critical insights:

  • The volume addresses why systems like the UMLS Metathesaurus fail to provide true integration, sometimes treating non-interchangeable entities (like 'aspirin' and 'Aspergum') as if they referred to the same concept in an "artificial world".
  • It exposes the flaws in systems like the National Cancer Institute Thesaurus (NCIT), demonstrating how it violates fundamental criteria for good classifications, such as disjointness or uniformity. For example, classifying 'cancer patient' and 'outpatient' as disjoint subtypes of 'patient' is problematic because many cancer patients are treated as outpatients.
  • The argument that type-level relations (such as $part_of$ between universals) must be rigorously defined by reverting to consideration of their instances is foundational. The precise delineation of four distinct $is_a$ relations—genus-subsumption, determinable-subsumption, specification, and specialization—resolves ambiguities that plague information systems.

Weaknesses: The authors acknowledge that the proposed transition to a realist orientation would be arduous, necessitating a global paradigm shift. Furthermore, the complexity of the domain—for example, the challenge of defining biological kinds given the "sheer number" of animal kinds (estimated at 30 million) and the existence of borderline cases—means that no classification system can be perfectly exhaustive. The core ideas, being novel in application, are still "being developed".

Connections to Broader Academic and Social Contexts

The book grounds its methodology in a broad sweep of philosophical history. It draws heavily on Aristotle's Categories to build a reliable top-level ontology, recommending the adoption of the Basic Formal Ontology (BFO) structure, influenced by Aristotelian ideas. The discussion of the four-category ontology (the ontological square, later expanded to a sextet) highlights the deep metaphysical concerns underlying effective information structure.

Academically, the volume directly combats influential non-realist positions. Ingvar Johansson's chapter explicitly clarifies and rejects alternative philosophies of science that discourage the pursuit of objective reality, specifically critiquing Myrdal’s Biasism and Vaihinger’s Fictionalism, in favor of Popper’s Epistemological Realism and its central notion of truthlikeness.

In a social and practical context, the book highlights immediate applications in health management. The lack of interoperability caused by non-standardized systems is a critical barrier. The proposed realist approach, particularly using Referent Tracking (assigning an instance unique identifier, or IUI, to every clinically relevant real-world entity), is presented as essential for linking information in Electronic Health Records (EHRs) to general scientific knowledge, thereby supporting diagnostics, scientific discovery, and public health surveillance.

Overall Contribution and Significance

"Applied Ontology: An Introduction" constitutes a seminal contribution to the emerging discipline of applied ontology. Its significance lies in its uncompromising stance that the intellectual rigor of philosophy is not a luxury but a necessary condition for overcoming the limitations of current, non-interoperable information systems. The book provides a theoretical blueprint, formal methodology, and clear practical guidelines for building reference ontologies that mirror reality.

The volume successfully demonstrates that foundational philosophical problems—such as what constitutes a natural kind or how processes unfold in time (occurrents)—have tangible practical consequences when building computerized systems. As the complexity and volume of scientific data continue to increase, the book’s argument that "the means by which knowledge is conveyed are every bit as important as that knowledge itself" serves as a powerful call to action.

Conclusion

This book is indispensable reading for information scientists, knowledge engineers, and bioinformaticians who are involved in developing, curating, or implementing controlled vocabularies and ontologies, particularly those within the biomedical domain.

It is also highly recommended for philosophers—especially those working in metaphysics, philosophy of science, and logic—as it showcases the profound and urgent practical relevance of their disciplines in the 21st century. The explicit intention of the volume is to improve systems for everyone whose life may be affected by scientific research, making its core principles vital for anyone concerned with the quality and reliability of digitally stored scientific knowledge.

 

Book Review: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

This comprehensive review is based entirely on the provided excerpts from the Revised Edition of A Theory of Justice by John Rawls.


Book Review: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

John Rawls’s A Theory of Justice (first published in 1971, with a revised edition incorporating significant improvements) is a landmark achievement in political and moral philosophy. Rawls sets out to construct a comprehensive theory of social justice, offering a "systematic alternative" to the utilitarian tradition that had long dominated Anglo-Saxon political thought. The result is a rigorous and detailed defense of "justice as fairness," designed as a philosophical foundation for constitutional democracy.

Overview of Main Themes, Arguments, and Structure

The central theme of the work is social justice, whose primary subject is the basic structure of society. This structure encompasses the major social institutions (like the political constitution and principal economic arrangements) and dictates the distribution of fundamental rights, duties, and advantages. Rawls famously declares that justice is the "first virtue of social institutions, as truth is of systems of thought".

Rawls develops his argument by generalizing the traditional concept of the social contract (associated with Locke, Rousseau, and Kant) to a "higher level of abstraction". He posits a hypothetical decision scenario, the Original Position, where free and rational persons choose the principles of justice. Crucially, this choice occurs behind a Veil of Ignorance, ensuring that no one knows their social status, natural abilities, or conception of the good. This device "ensures that no one is advantaged or disadvantaged in the choice of principles by the outcome of natural chance or the contingency of social circumstances". The idea is that the resulting principles are the outcome of a fair agreement, explaining the name "justice as fairness".

Rawls argues that the parties in the Original Position would select Two Principles of Justice in lexical (serial) order:

  1. The Equal Basic Liberties Principle: "Each person is to have an equal right to the most extensive scheme of equal basic liberties compatible with a similar scheme of liberties for others".
  2. The Difference Principle and Fair Equality of Opportunity: Social and economic inequalities must be arranged so they are both (a) "reasonably expected to be to everyone’s advantage" (interpreted as maximizing the expectations of the least advantaged—the Difference Principle) and (b) attached to offices open to all under conditions of fair equality of opportunity.

The lexical priority means that basic liberties cannot be infringed upon or compromised for the sake of greater social or economic advantages. This priority is a crucial element that distinguishes justice as fairness from utilitarianism, which might permit "the violation of the liberty of a few" if it resulted in "the greater good shared by many". Rawls fundamentally argues that utilitarianism does not take seriously the distinction between persons.

The book is structured into three parts: Part One: Theory (establishing the core concepts, the two principles, and the Original Position); Part Two: Institutions (applying the principles to constitutional frameworks, political economy, and duties/obligations, including the famous discussion of civil disobedience); and Part Three: Ends (developing the necessary theory of the good to support the premises, exploring moral psychology, and arguing for the congruence of the right and the good).

Analysis of Style, Tone, and Perspective

Rawls adopts a highly systematic and theoretical style, aiming to unify "the ideas expressed in the papers I have written over the past dozen years or so". The tone is rigorously analytical, characterized by philosophical precision and careful terminology (e.g., distinguishing between the concept of justice and conceptions of justice, or between the duty of justice and the obligation of fairness).

Rawls's perspective is fundamentally Kantian. He sees the Original Position as a "procedural interpretation of Kant’s conception of autonomy and the categorical imperative". Acting justly is understood as acting from principles one would consent to as a "free and equal rational being". The theory uses "simplifying devices" and assumes certain general facts (including psychological principles) to create a framework that yields definite results, striving for a "moral geometry".

A notable aspect of the author’s perspective is his commitment to intellectual honesty, as demonstrated in the preface to the revised edition. Rawls notes that criticisms, such as those made by H. L. A. Hart regarding the account of liberty, prompted "significant improvements" to the text. He also corrects what he terms a "serious mistake in the argument for the priority of liberty" and indicates that certain arguments (like those for the Difference Principle) are "less evident" than others.

Evaluation of Strengths and Weaknesses

The central strength of A Theory of Justice is its success in presenting a "workable and systematic moral conception to oppose" utilitarianism and intuitionism, which Rawls found deficient. By placing the priority of liberty first, the theory establishes that the rights secured by justice "are not subject to political bargaining or to the calculus of social interests". This secures "the basic liberties of a democratic regime" most firmly.

A major internal critical insight is encapsulated in Rawls’s response to utilitarianism, which he argues applies the principle of rational choice for one person to society as a whole, thereby "conflating all persons into one". The contract doctrine, conversely, takes "seriously the plurality and distinctness of individuals".

Rawls himself points out several initial weaknesses addressed in the revised edition:

  • The original account of primary goods was ambiguous, needing clarification that they are characterized by what "persons need in their status as free and equal citizens" rather than solely psychological facts.
  • The initial formulation of the argument for the two principles was structurally improved to better separate the strong case for equal liberties from the case for the difference principle.
  • He notes he would handle the presentation of the institutional framework differently by distinguishing more "sharply the idea of a property-owning democracy... from the idea of a welfare state".

Another challenge the book tackles explicitly is the reliance on intuition. Rawls acknowledges that philosophical justification often leads back to intuition when weighing competing principles (the difficulty of "intuitionism"). His solution, however, is to employ the concept of reflective equilibrium—a state where our principles and our considered judgments of justice are brought into "mutual support" and coherence. By providing rigorous constructive criteria, Rawls argues the theory reduces the dependence on unguided intuition.

Connections to Broader Contexts

A Theory of Justice serves as a profound intervention in academic discourse, positioning itself as the culmination of the social contract tradition while actively refuting the utilitarian school. It integrates concerns from various disciplines:

  • Political Economy: Rawls applies his principles directly to economic arrangements, policies, and background institutions, discussing ideas like economic efficiency, public goods, and the appropriate function of the transfer branch in guaranteeing a social minimum.
  • Legal/Political Theory: It provides a moral framework for constitutional law, discussing the necessity of the Rule of Law (formal justice) and scrutinizing core democratic institutions like majority rule. The detailed discussion of civil disobedience within a nearly just society is particularly significant, defining it as a "public, nonviolent, conscientious yet political act contrary to law" aimed at appealing to the community's sense of justice.
  • Moral Psychology: Part Three connects the choice of political principles to the social nature of humankind, arguing that a sense of justice is a natural psychological development in a well-ordered society. The stability of the just society relies on the belief that possessing an effective sense of justice belongs to a person’s own good (congruence).

In a social and cultural context, the theory provides an ideal—an "Archimedean point"—from which to critique existing societal arrangements. The principle of fair opportunity, for example, challenges the notion that distributive shares should be determined by the "natural lottery" of talents or social contingencies. Rawls argues that his framework provides a basis for the worth of liberty to the least advantaged, demonstrating that the resulting inequalities are acceptable because they enhance the capacity of the less fortunate to achieve their aims.

Overall Contribution and Significance

The book's overall contribution is monumental: it successfully revived and systematized contract theory to deliver a robust, deontological account of liberal egalitarianism. It provides a moral basis for democratic society, emphasizing that the inviolability of each person is "founded on justice that even the welfare of society as a whole cannot override".

By defining the just society (ideal theory) and providing the tools to analyze deviations (nonideal theory), Rawls furnishes a rigorous and comprehensive standard. The final chapters solidify this by arguing that the just principles support our moral self-worth: "The unity of the self is essentially related to the rightness of the principles of justice" . Furthermore, the theory accommodates the "values of community" through the idea of a well-ordered society as a "social union of social unions," where the successful operation of just institutions becomes a shared final end.

Conclusion: Target Audience

A Theory of Justice is essential reading for individuals engaging with the deepest questions of political legitimacy and moral foundation.

It would most benefit academic readers—especially those in political philosophy, ethics, law, and social theory—due to its systematic, abstract nature, detailed engagement with complex ideas (like utilitarian calculus and maximin reasoning), and foundational role in modern discourse. It serves as a necessary benchmark for understanding contemporary theories of rights, equality, and distribution.

Beyond the academy, the book is highly valuable for thoughtful citizens, policy makers, and legal scholars in constitutional democracies who seek a definitive moral justification for civil liberties, distributive systems, and public institutions. Its clarity on issues like the justification of civil disobedience (in a nearly just regime) provides crucial guidance for applying political principles in moments of social conflict. However, readers must approach the text with patience, as Rawls acknowledges it is a "long book" requiring close attention, particularly to core concepts like the Original Position and the two principles.

Epistemology: A Detailed and Analytical Book Review

Epistemology: A Detailed and Analytical Book Review

Robert Audi's Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction to the Theory of Knowledge (first published in 1998) is widely recognized as a major contribution to the field, lauded as a "state-of-the-art introduction" by leading figures. The book provides a lucid, comprehensive, and well-structured survey of the theory of knowledge and justification.

I. Main Themes, Author’s Purpose, and Intellectual Context

The central concern of epistemology, as conceived by Audi, is answering how we know what we do, what justifies us in believing what we do, and what standards of evidence we should employ in seeking truths.

Author’s Purpose and Scope: Audi, an internationally recognized leading author in epistemology, designed the book primarily for intermediate and advanced undergraduates and starting graduate students, though it is also valuable for professional colleagues. It is intended for readers who have completed at least one introductory philosophy course. The primary aim is instructional: to educate readers in the major philosophical problems, positions, and arguments in contemporary epistemology, providing tools necessary to understand both classical and modern texts. While he seeks to introduce the field neutrally, Audi also sympathetically considers a variety of positions while defending his own preferred solutions. The overall approach is to "do epistemology rather than talk about it".

Main Themes and Arguments: The book’s comprehensive scope is structured around three main conceptual phases:

  1. Sources: Identifying the origins of belief, justification, and knowledge (perception, memory, consciousness, reason, testimony).
  2. Structure and Development: Exploring how knowledge is extended (inference) and organized (foundationalism vs. coherentism).
  3. Nature and Scope: Analyzing what knowledge is (the Gettier problem, internalism vs. externalism) and evaluating its reach into specific domains (science, ethics, religion, and skepticism).

Audi consistently champions the concept of justification as equally important as knowledge itself. A critical thread running through the later chapters is the distinction between Internalism (justification is internally accessible, e.g., via introspection or reflection) and Externalism (knowledge is often externally grounded in reliability or causal processes not accessible to the subject).

Intellectual Context and Relevance: Published toward the end of the 20th century, Epistemology sits within a contemporary philosophical landscape dominated by post-Gettier analyses of knowledge, reliability theories, and fierce debates over the structure of justification (e.g., between foundationalists and coherentists). Audi is informed by the tradition (mentioning Plato, Descartes, Hume, Kant, Mill, etc.) but structures the discussion around current analytical arguments. The intellectual context involves responding to skepticism, which Audi places last, arguing that skepticism should not distract non-professional readers from conceptual questions concerning knowledge itself. Its clear articulation of these enduring and complex debates ensures its continued relevance today.

II. Chapter-by-Chapter Breakdown of Key Ideas

The book is organized into three parts across ten chapters, reflecting a "natural progression" through the field:

Part One: Sources of Justification, Knowledge, and Truth

  • Chapter 1: Perception: Defines perception largely as a causal relation involving the perceiver, the object, sensory experience, and the causal link. It details the modes of perception (simple, objectual/to be, and propositional/that). Audi argues against sense-datum theories, favoring direct realist views like the Theory of Appearing or the Adverbial Theory, which account for illusion and hallucination without positing inner mental objects. Perception is established as a basic source of belief, justification, and knowledge.
  • Chapter 2: Memory: Compares memory to perception, noting its role in preserving information acquired through the senses. Audi differentiates the function of memory, noting it is a basic source of justification (as memorial impressions can be justified even if false) but mainly a preservative source of knowledge, as knowledge cannot be gained from memory unless it was acquired previously in another way (e.g., perception).
  • Chapter 3: Consciousness: Explores introspection as a source of self-knowledge. Audi argues that introspective consciousness is a basic source of justification and knowledge, analogous to perception. However, he challenges the strong doctrine of privileged access (the theses of infallibility and omniscience), suggesting attentive introspective beliefs are merely normally true and justified, not absolutely infallible.
  • Chapter 4: Reason: Focuses on truths knowable a priori (independently of experience) through conceptual understanding, centered on the notion of self-evidence. Audi contrasts the Classical View (Rationalism, endorsing synthetic a priori truths) with Empiricism (Mill) and Conventionalism. He argues that reason, as a capacity of understanding, is a basic and active source of justification and knowledge, enabling us to know truths that hold in any circumstances.
  • Chapter 5: Testimony: Posited as the primary social source of justification and knowledge. Audi distinguishes between the Inferentialist View and the view that testimony produces non-inferential beliefs that are merely filtered by background knowledge. A key argument is that testimony is not a basic source of knowledge or belief because it is operationally dependent on perception (to hear or read the testimony). It functions primarily to transmit knowledge (requiring the attester to know) but can generate justification (requiring the recipient to be credible).

Part Two: The Structure and Growth of Justification and Knowledge

  • Chapter 6: Inference and the Extension of Knowledge: Explains that inference extends and transmits justification and knowledge, but is not a basic source itself, as it relies on premises that must already be justified or known. Audi details how knowledge/justification transmit across both deductive (requiring validity) and inductive inferences (requiring strength, but with potential for diminution of justification).
  • Chapter 7: The Architecture of Knowledge: Addresses the Epistemic Regress Problem. Audi concludes that foundational beliefs, or basic beliefs directly anchored in experience or reason, are necessary if knowledge is to occur. He argues for Moderate Foundationalism, a view that accepts the fallibility and defeasibility of foundational beliefs and incorporates a significant, albeit non-basic, role for coherence. He critiques Holistic Coherentism for struggling with the "isolation problem"—explaining why a coherent system of beliefs should correspond to truth.

Part Three: The Nature and Scope of Justification and Knowledge

  • Chapter 8: The Analysis of Knowledge: Focuses on the question "What is knowledge?". After showing the inadequacy of the traditional Justified True Belief (JTB) analysis, Audi explores alternatives, including Naturalistic Accounts (Causal and Reliability theories). He discusses cases that challenge the necessity of justification for knowledge (e.g., "natural knowledge" in the idiot savant or clairvoyance). This leads to the crucial dichotomy between Internalism (preferable for justification, which is accessible to the subject) and Externalism (preferable for knowledge, which requires reliable, objective grounding). He proposes that knowledge is "true belief based in the right way on the right kind of ground".
  • Chapter 9: Scientific, Moral, and Religious Knowledge: Examines the scope of knowledge in three major domains. Scientific knowledge is characterized by fallibilism and is often merely approximate knowledge or knowledge of approximations, achieved through methods like inference to the best explanation. Moral knowledge is defensible against relativism and noncognitivism, grounding itself either a priori (Intuitionism/Kantianism) or empirically (Utilitarianism). Religious knowledge is assessed by contrasting Evidentialism with Experientialism (the possibility of direct, non-inferential knowledge of God). Audi argues that rationality is a weaker, more attainable status than justification for beliefs in these domains.
  • Chapter 10: Skepticism: Reserved for the final comprehensive discussion. Audi addresses radical doubts concerning direct and inferential knowledge, including the Problem of Induction and the Problem of Other Minds. He systematically analyzes and argues against core skeptical principles (e.g., the Infallibility Principle and the Certainty Principle). He aims for a rebuttal of skepticism—showing the skeptical arguments do not establish that we lack knowledge—rather than an outright refutation (showing skepticism is false). He concludes that the commonsense view that we possess vast knowledge is rationally resistible but is certainly not defeated by these core skeptical arguments.

III. Author’s Style, Clarity, and Use of Evidence

Audi's text is praised by reviewers for its exemplary clarity and structure. He is described as a "master expositor" whose writing is "lucid and highly readable". The style is accessible, clear, and stimulating, striving to be "simple and concrete" without sacrificing philosophical rigor.

Clarity and Structure: The organizational structure of moving from sources to structure to scope is highly effective, leading the reader in a "natural progression". Audi meticulously explains complex concepts, providing definitions or explications for most major epistemological terms, marked by boldface in the index for easy reference.

Use of Evidence: Audi draws evidence from thought experiments, philosophical traditions, and common-sense scenarios (e.g., the field before him, the hallucinating Macbeth, and the sweepstakes case) to illustrate intricate distinctions, such as between situational justification and belief justification, or between knowledge and justification (Chapter 8). He considers diverse positions fairly and sympathetically before presenting his favored solutions.

IV. Comparison with Other Works and Contribution

Epistemology is noted as being among the "best and most comprehensive introductions to epistemology". It is distinct in its ambition to be a systematic, contemporary introduction informed by tradition, rather than merely a commentary on literature.

Comparison with Genre: As an introduction designed to bridge introductory philosophy with higher-level coursework, the book comprehensively covers crucial debates (foundationalism, coherentism, internalism, externalism) typical of the genre but integrates them uniquely within Audi's distinct, moderate perspective. Unlike many traditional approaches, Audi postpones the main assessment of skepticism until the final chapter, believing that epistemological concepts are independently interesting and should be understood before the question of their existence is debated fully.

Critical Reflection on Contribution: The book provides a powerful case for a form of Moderate Foundationalism that avoids the dogmatism of earlier Cartesian foundationalism. Its most significant contribution to understanding the subject is the systematic distinction drawn between justification and knowledge, arguing that the former tends toward an internalist understanding (based on subjectively accessible grounds like sensory experience) while the latter demands an externalist framework (based on objective reliability for truth). This dual approach allows Audi to respect the necessity of individual rational responsibility while maintaining the objectivist constraints of truth and reliable connection to reality required for genuine knowledge.

V. Target Readership

The book is an "invaluable resource" for several groups:

  • Intermediate and advanced undergraduates and starting graduates will find it comprehensive and accessible, offering a strong foundation in core problems and contemporary theory.
  • General readers in epistemology at any level can utilize its clarity and scope.
  • Professional colleagues find it of considerable interest.
  • Students pursuing collateral reading in the philosophy of mind or reading key historical philosophers (such as Descartes, Hume, Kant, or Mill) will benefit from Audi’s explanations of interconnected concepts like perception, introspection, and moral epistemology.

 

Book Review: Philosophy of Social Science (Second Edition)

The following is a detailed and analytical review of Philosophy of Social Science (Second Edition) by Ted Benton and Ian Craib.


Book Review: Philosophy of Social Science (Second Edition)

Authors: Ted Benton and Ian Craib

Main Themes, Arguments, and Author’s Purpose

Philosophy of Social Science (Second Edition) serves primarily as a concise introduction and "language primer" to the philosophical traditions and contentious arguments surrounding the study of human social life. The central purpose of the work is to encourage students of social science to engage in reflexive inquiry by addressing the fundamental question: "What are we doing when we attempt to study human social life in a systematic way?". The authors, drawing on a long history of intellectual collaboration and debate, present a complex, nuanced picture of the social sciences, arguing that philosophical questions are not externally imposed but arise intrinsically from the "special difficulties and deep disagreements" found within the disciplines themselves.

The main arguments revolve around charting the philosophical terrain (epistemology, ontology, logic, ethics) and navigating the perennial tension between naturalistic (positivist) approaches that model social science on natural science, and anti-naturalistic (interpretivist) approaches that emphasize meaning, culture, and subjectivity.

Crucially, the book argues against a simple dichotomy, dedicating significant space to developing and defending alternative, post-empiricist models of science, notably Critical Realism, which seeks to overcome the sterile opposition between meaning and cause, or particular versus universal methods. The authors frame their endeavor as "underlabouring" for the social sciences—providing clarity, criticizing prejudices, mapping existing knowledge, and refining methods.

Chapter-by-Chapter Breakdown

The book is structured to move logically from traditional philosophical debates concerning natural science toward contemporary debates specifically within social theory, before returning to a synthesis in the context of critical realism and critique.

Part I: The Natural Science Model and Its Critics (Chapters 1–4)

  • Chapter 1 (Introduction): Establishes the necessity of philosophy, detailing the "masterbuilder" versus "underlabourer" views. It introduces the "philosophical toolkit": Epistemology (the theory of knowledge, contrasting rationalism and empiricism), Ontology (the theory of what exists, contrasting materialism and idealism), Logic, and Ethics/Moral Philosophy.
  • Chapter 2 (Empiricism and Positivism in Science): Outlines the empiricist account of knowledge through seven basic doctrines, emphasizing testability, the reliance on observation/experiment, and the 'covering law' model of explanation. Positivism is characterized by extending these methods to the study of social life (naturalism) and the notion of "social engineering". A strength of this chapter is its clear demarcation of key concepts, but it highlights the inherent difficulty in drawing a clear dividing line between science and 'pseudo-science' using strict testability criteria.
  • Chapter 3 (Some Problems of Empiricism and Positivism): This chapter provides extensive critiques of empiricism, highlighting that observations are conceptually mediated ("theory dependence of observation"). It tackles the problem of induction and notes the distinction between confirmation and Popper’s falsification. It discusses incommensurability (rival theories talking past each other). A key strength is the introduction of different roles for theory: functional, historical-narrative, and the hypothetico-deductive model, which challenges the empiricist "flat ontology" by suggesting reality is layered.
  • Chapter 4 (Science, Nature and Society: Some Alternatives to Empiricism): Reviews post-empiricist alternatives, emphasizing the social and historical location of science. Key ideas include the Frankfurt School's critique (science as domination), Merton’s institutional imperatives for science, the French tradition of Historical Epistemology (epistemological breaks), Kuhn’s concept of the paradigm and scientific revolutions, and the Strong Programme (impartiality and symmetry). A weakness is noted in the early formulation of Actor-Network Theory, which tended toward cynicism and rejected reason itself.

Part II: Interpretive Approaches (Chapters 5–7)

These chapters explore the arguments that social sciences must adopt distinct methods due to the nature of their objects (self-conscious, reflexive human beings).

  • Chapter 5 (Interpretive Approaches 1: Instrumental Rationality): Focuses on instrumental rationality (action directed towards practical, achievable ends). The pivotal thinker is Max Weber, who defined the object of sociology as "meaningful, rational, social action" and used ideal types and verstehen (interpretive understanding). Weber's criteria for judgment are meaning adequacy and causal adequacy (through comparative analysis). Related approaches include Phenomenology (Schutz’s typifications/second-order typifications), and Rational Choice Theory (maximizing profit/benefits). The strength lies in establishing the hermeneutic starting point, although the chapter notes the inherent difficulty in equating reasons with causes.
  • Chapter 6 (Interpretive Approaches 2: Rationality as Rule-Following): Moves beyond individual meaning to collective culture. Peter Winch's influential argument, rooted in Wittgenstein, states that concepts settle the form of experience and that social life is rule-following. Since rules can be followed wrongly or rightly, social action cannot be understood through causal explanations. The chapter explores the resulting relativism and introduces Alisdair MacIntyre’s emphasis on morality rooted in tradition and human life understood through narratives. Finally, Gadamer’s Hermeneutics stresses the historical nature of understanding and the hermeneutic circle (part-to-whole movement). A weakness is Gadamer’s potential conservatism and overemphasis on the authority of tradition, which hinders the critique of ideologies.
  • Chapter 7 (Interpretive Approaches 3: Critical Rationality): Focuses on critique and emancipation. It introduces the Dialectic (Hegel/Marx) and the Frankfurt School's concept of Ideology (systematically distorted ideas, resulting in "second nature"). Habermas attempts a synthesis, organizing social scientific approaches around three cognitive interests (technical, practical, emancipatory). Habermas's model—which posits the ideal speech situation and communicative rationality as democratic standards—offers a strong alternative to relativism.

Part III: New Directions (Chapters 8–10) and Conclusion

  • Chapter 8 (Critical Realism and the Social Sciences): Presents Critical Realism (CR) as a non-positivist, yet realist alternative. CR asserts that reality is stratified (real/mechanisms, actual/events, empirical/observations) and differentiates between the intransitive dimension (independent reality) and the transitive dimension (conceptual, social process of knowledge production). It advocates a critical naturalism for social science. Crucially, it proposes the transformational model of social action to resolve the structure/agency problem, and argues that knowledge can support emancipation through explanatory critique (identifying social structures that cause suffering or false beliefs).
  • Chapter 9 (Feminism, Knowledge and Society): Examines the challenges posed by feminism to traditional epistemology, especially regarding objectivity and universality. It contrasts Feminist Empiricism with Feminist Standpoint Epistemology (S. Harding, H. Rose, N. Hartsock), which argues that marginalized social positions yield more adequate knowledge (a critique of "malestream" science). The chapter notes the internal feminist critique from Post-modern Feminism, which rejects the universal category "woman" and epistemology itself.
  • Chapter 10 (Post-structuralism and Post-modernism): Examines the shift from structuralism (underlying structures, linguistic analogy) to Post-structuralism (Foucault's discourse/power-knowledge and Derrida's deconstruction/logocentrism). Post-modernism (Lyotard) denies the possibility of meta-narratives, emphasizing fragmentation, plurality, and skepticism toward foundational truths. The critical reflection here acknowledges the 'posts' intellectual provocation but argues that the abandonment of reason is self-refuting, as critique must employ the Enlightenment principles it denies.
  • Chapter 11 (Conclusion: In Defence of Philosophy): Re-emphasizes the complexity of the social world, advocating for intellectual life beyond simple instrumental thinking. It argues that philosophical reflection on scientific practice justifies key distinctions, such as critical realism’s transitive/intransitive dimensions, and asserts that social structures exist independently of our concepts.
  • Chapter 12 (Commentary on Recent Developments): Added by Benton for the Second Edition (Ian Craib having died in 2002). This chapter provides explicit critical commentary, particularly focusing on the debate surrounding Peter Winch's anti-scientism and discussing the development of post-Marxist discourse theory (Glynos and Howarth). It highlights the proliferation of work in the critical realist tradition since the first edition, including debates on methodology, the structure/agency problem, and Bhaskar's "spiritual turn".

Historical and Intellectual Context

The book is deeply rooted in the intellectual ferment following the Enlightenment, dealing directly with the legacies of Rationalism and Empiricism. The authors’ intellectual biographies place them in the generation of the "sixties," sharing an initial strong political and moral commitment, particularly to Marxism. This background meant they were concerned throughout their careers with adapting social theory to the massive intellectual and political challenges presented by movements such as feminism, environmentalism, and anti-racism. The philosophical differences between the authors—Ian Craib’s focus on subjectivity, psychoanalysis, and anti-naturalism, and Ted Benton’s commitment to naturalism, critical realism, and life sciences—structured the book’s division of labor and its pervasive internal debate.

The book’s structure reflects the movement in philosophy of social science away from the mid-20th-century dominance of logical positivism and the rise of alternatives like post-Kuhnian philosophy of science, which emphasizes the social practice of science.

Relevance Today: The relevance of the book remains high because it addresses persistent issues: the tension between scientific explanation and human meaning, the role of values in objective research, and the possibility of rational critique in a relativistic world. Chapter 12 ensures contemporary relevance by engaging with recent developments in critical realism and post-structuralism/post-Marxism, showing how these theoretical traditions continue to evolve and clash.

Evaluation of Author’s Style, Clarity, and Use of Evidence

The authors successfully achieve the tone of a comprehensive "primer" and "map" of the field. The writing maintains a "careful and respectful attitude to alternative points of view". Ian Craib’s contributions are lauded for their ability to communicate complex and difficult ideas in a direct and accessible way, capturing the "sense of excitement and bewilderment" of intellectual exploration.

The use of evidence is primarily conceptual and historical. The authors meticulously reconstruct the intellectual journeys that led to key philosophical stances (e.g., tracing Kantian ideas to Weberian methodology, or Lukácsian ideas to feminist standpoint theory). They employ transcendental arguments (Bhaskar) as evidence for ontological claims about reality. They use concrete examples—like Darwin’s natural selection, the ambiguity of visual perception, or the Azande witchcraft debate—to make abstract philosophical points clear. The critical reflection notes that the book "depends on a real philosophical argument" rather than empirical investigation of any single discipline, enhancing its role as a work of philosophy.

Comparison with Other Works

The book positions itself as a companion to foundational theoretical texts and introduces multiple traditions concisely. By systematically reviewing and critiquing Empiricism (Popper, Ayer) and Positivism (Comte, Durkheim), before diving into interpretive traditions (Weber, Winch, Gadamer, Habermas), the book covers the territory expected of a philosophy of social science text.

However, its strength lies in moving beyond the traditional positivism/hermeneutics binary by promoting post-empiricist, non-reductive approaches, specifically Critical Realism. In doing so, it engages with contemporary social theory (e.g., Giddens's structuration theory, which is discussed as a different approach to the structure/agency problem than the critical realist transformational model). It explicitly compares its mission to the foundational philosophical work of thinkers like Gramsci.

Critical Reflection and Target Audience

The greatest contribution of Philosophy of Social Science is its rigorous argument for sustained philosophical reflection within the social sciences, demonstrating that the deepest methodological disputes stem from fundamental disagreements over epistemology and ontology. It contributes significantly by showing that natural science itself is not monolithic, allowing for the possibility of a "scientific" social study that rejects the narrow, surface-level focus of traditional positivism.

The book's refusal to offer settled conclusions, instead inviting the reader to participate in the debate—to "argue against yourself from alternative points of view"—is a key strength. It makes the powerful case that intellectual life and the struggle for understanding are themselves inherently valuable and emancipatory.

Target Readers and Researchers: The book is ideal for students and apprentices to the social sciences. It specifically benefits those seeking a framework to:

  1. Situate their discipline within wider philosophical traditions (e.g., sociology, economics, history, psychology).
  2. Understand the philosophical foundations of competing theoretical approaches, such as rational choice theory, feminism, or post-structuralism.
  3. Engage in advanced research by clarifying methodological presuppositions, particularly those seeking to integrate meaning/interpretation with causal/structural explanation (e.g., researchers interested in Critical Realism, critical theory, or issues of power and ideology).
  4. Reflect critically on the moral and political implications of their work, moving beyond simple factual investigation to normative evaluation.

 

Fatalism and Development: Nepal’s Struggle for Modernization by Dor Bahadur Bista: A Comprehensive Review

Dor Bahadur Bista’s Fatalism and Development: Nepal’s Struggle for Modernization (1991) offers a bold, insightful, and profoundly critical analysis of the deeply rooted socio-cultural impediments hindering Nepal’s progress. The book, described as having the philosophical flavor of attempts like Max Weber's Protestant Ethic or Alexis de Tocqueville's Ancien Régime, is considered essential for understanding the complexities of modernization in the Himalayan nation.

Overview of the Author and His Perspective

Dor Bahadur Bista is acknowledged as Nepal’s leading social anthropologist. Born in 1928 in Lalitpur, Nepal, he received a broad education in Kathmandu, London, and Wisconsin. Bista brought a unique perspective to this work, cultivated through his experiences as the first professor of anthropology at Tribhuvan University, his various teaching assignments across international universities, and his extensive involvement in business and developmental activities within Nepal.

Crucially, Bista writes as a "sympathetic yet critical insider" who acquired a deep understanding of Nepal’s complex ethnic mix through extensive travel, including time spent in the company of leading anthropologist Christoph von Furer-Haimendorf. His position as an insider grants him the ability to offer objective and frank commentary and "say things which no outsider could say" about the internal struggles of his country. The book attempts to diagnose Nepal's ills by examining how deeply entrenched values, particularly among the elite, compromise the potential for modernization.

Detailed Summary of Main Arguments and Themes

Bista argues that Nepal’s struggle for modernization is fundamentally a cultural one. Nepal is a heteronomous society comprising a complex ethnic mix. Within this diversity, many indigenous ethnic groups possess "positive social qualities" conducive to development, such as a strong commitment to productive labour, high capacity for endurance, efficient cooperative organizational styles, and high adaptive propensity.

However, these indigenous strengths are increasingly suppressed and endangered by an "alien culture": the culture of fatalism. This fatalistic culture is inherently in conflict with development because it devalues the concept of productivity.

The bulk of Bista’s argument centers on the corrupting influence of this fatalistic culture, which he associates primarily with the "cumbersome and ossified structure" of the urbane upper-class and high-caste Hindu society of the Kathmandu Valley. Key negative institutions and belief systems identified are:

  1. Fatalism: The absolute belief that one has no personal control over life circumstances, which are determined by a powerful external agency or divinity—often encapsulated in the concept of karma. In this worldview, karma is seen as predestined and unalterable by present action.
  2. Dependency: Fatalism is highly connected to various forms of dependency. This vertical dependence emphasizes a continuing superordinate-subordinate relationship that extends outside the family into society.
  3. Afno Manchhe ("One's Own People"): This institution is a pervasive social circle of associates essential for security and success. While reflecting traditional collectivism, afno manchhe readily subverts institutional goals, fostering problems of inclusion-exclusion, factionalism, and corruption.
  4. Chakari (Sycophancy): Defined as a passive, instrumental behavior aimed at demonstrating dependency to elicit favor from a powerful person. Originating in religious ritual, it was formalized by the Ranas and persists today. Persistence in chakari is seen as merit, replacing the efficient fulfillment of duties. Bista insists that chakari "must be purged if economic success is to be a reality in Nepal".

Bista argues that Nepal’s strengths have historically rested on the indigenous qualities of its ethnic groups, but that modernization has been defeated by the attempts at "Indianization" of its culture, specifically the negative, hierarchic aspects of caste culture (Bahunism).

Critical Analysis of Fatalism and Development Challenges

The culture of fatalism directly undermines the mechanisms necessary for modernization and growth.

The most significant consequence is the devastating effect on the work ethic and achievement motivation. Because one's destiny is fated, personal effort seems pointless; instead, individuals focus on accumulating religious merit. High-caste individuals consequently despise physical labor, equating work (dukkha) with pain. Their goal is a salaried job (Jagir) where one does not have to work but still receives a paycheck, viewing a high position as a reward to be enjoyed rather than a duty to society. This results in a lack of productive effort among the educated elite.

Fatalism also compromises Nepal’s capacity for planning and temporal orientation. Nepali culture lacks a strong sense of time as discrete or linear, viewing it instead as an "endless present". The future is only taken seriously in the sense of the "life hereafter," discouraging pragmatic planning for economic stability or old age. This leads to a consummatory orientation—squandering resources immediately without consideration for the future, leading to perpetual reliance on foreign investment.

Furthermore, fatalism affects the sense of responsibility. Since control is external (divine or external administrative forces), responsibility is displaced. The individual does not feel bound to keep contractual relations because agreements are completed only if they were fated to be completed.

In relation to foreign aid, fatalism reinforces dependence. Foreign aid is often perceived not as a resource for productive growth, but as a "divinely instigated redistribution" that is "justly due to Nepal". When development fails, the tendency is to blame external circumstances or the powerful foreign donors themselves, maintaining "a childlike innocence" on the part of the Nepali elite. The combination of dependency, chakari, and fatalism results in government processes that are built-in guarantors of incompetence, inefficiency, and misplaced effort.

Historical, Cultural, and Political Context

The book was written during a significant period of political flux. The typescript was completed in the summer of 1989, following nearly four decades after the overthrow of the Rana prime ministers in 1950, which ended Nepal's isolation as a medieval society. Bista notes that the period between 1989 and 1990 saw "remarkable changes in the political system of the country". The chapter on 'Politics and Government' was updated around June 1990, reflecting the introduction of the liberal and democratic multi-party system.

Culturally, the book is centered on the cultural systems of the major groups of the high caste Hindus. The caste system, first appearing marginally in the Licchavi era, was imposed largely by local ruling elites who applied Bahunistic principles to entrench their class status. The negative influence of this caste culture became pervasive during the middle of the nineteenth century.

Politically, the book examines the failures of various imported systems (parliamentary, Panchayat) to adapt to the national character, particularly the pervasive paternal dependency. This dependency ensures that authority resides ultimately with the monarch, viewed as a protective father figure, making the King a central focus for chakari. Bista critiques the administrative chaos that evolved, noting that the investment in a large bureaucratic apparatus far exceeded the development of the necessary technical-economic infrastructure.

Impact, Relevance, Critiques, and Controversies

Fatalism and Development challenged prevailing scholarly views. Bista explicitly denied the historical notion that "Nepal is India in the making" and instead asserted that Nepal's developmental problems stem from the attempted Indianization of its culture, specifically through the imposition of Hindu caste culture. He also critiqued Western theoretical frameworks, which often obscured issues concerning value systems by focusing too heavily on Indian caste models or capitalist periphery theories.

Bista anticipated significant controversy and critique from within the dominant high-caste groups, noting that many educated members are unaware of their own culture's negative impact. He observed that critics often prefer to focus on "politico-economic aspects" rather than confronting the socio-cultural and religious values imposed upon the national society. The book is controversial for directly identifying the high-caste Hindu elite (Bahun-Chhetri) as the primary agents perpetuating the debilitating value system.

The book’s relevance today is affirmed by Bista himself, who noted in 1990 that the fundamental socio-cultural value system of Nepali society "still remains" as described. The shift to democracy only offered possibilities for change, and the future success "is yet to be seen". The persistence of the fatalistic attitude, which can be secularized and perpetuated even by non-caste individuals seeking status, suggests that the challenges Bista identified remain central to Nepal's ongoing struggle for stability and prosperity.

Reflections for Readers and Scholars

Readers and scholars gain a crucial understanding of modernization as a process not just of technological transfer or political structuring, but of profound cultural transformation. Bista emphasizes that Nepal's path to development must be indigenous.

Key lessons include:

  • The Power of Values: The book demonstrates how a core, debilitating value system (fatalism) can penetrate and subvert imported modern institutions (bureaucracy, education, foreign aid), turning tools designed for efficiency into mechanisms for reinforcing dependency and status.
  • The Hidden Resource: Scholars must recognize that Nepal's greatest resource is its ethnic population. These groups (such as the Kirat, Gurung, and Magar) possess inherent qualities—hard work, endurance, cooperation—that are vital for development and offer greater flexibility than the ossified high-caste structure.
  • Need for Internalized Change: Modernization requires Nepalis to internalize responsibility, overcome the "archaic values of hierarchic caste discipline," and liberate themselves from cultural mores that punish productive labor.
  • Challenging the Status Quo: The book urges intellectual honesty to resist the imposition of a fatalistic hierarchic social order, arguing that such values are irreconcilable with genuine development. By quantifying the negative consequences of chakari, afno manchhe, and fatalism, Bista provides a framework for diagnosing bureaucratic and political incompetence in developing nations rooted not in lack of skill, but in cultural practice.

Tuesday, October 7, 2025

Philosophy of social science: the philosophical foundations of social thought by Ted Benton and Ian Craib

The provided text is comprised of excerpts from the second edition of a book titled "Philosophy of Social Science" by Ted Benton and Ian Craib, with the preface and commentary written by Benton following Craib's death. The authors primarily address the relationship between philosophy and the social sciences, exploring various theoretical traditions and methodological debates, such as empiricism, positivism, interpretivism, critical theory, feminism, and critical realism. The book serves as an overview of major approaches, examining how social sciences differ from or align with the natural sciences, discussing concepts like ontology, epistemology, and different types of rationality (especially instrumental rationality). It also includes a personal reflection and obituary for co-author Ian Craib, highlighting his contributions to sociological humanism and psychoanalysis.

----------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------

This comprehensive book review examines Philosophy of Social Science (Second Edition) by Ted Benton and Ian Craib, a volume in the Traditions in Social Theory series. The book is a product of a long-running dialogue between the authors, originating from a course they taught together over twenty-five years.

Summary of Main Arguments

The central purpose of this study is to address the foundational philosophical questions facing social scientists, particularly: "What are we doing when we attempt to study human social life in a systematic way?". The book is presented as a collection of arguments rather than a source of settled conclusions.

The core intellectual project is to move beyond the traditional, often "sterile and inconclusive" opposition between positivism (the naturalistic orientation) and interpretivism (the hermeneutic approach). The authors argue that a deep understanding of philosophical debates, including those concerning the natural sciences, is indispensable for social sciences. They explore whether social sciences can be studied scientifically, even if not using the same methods as the natural sciences, by drawing on alternative, non-empiricist models of science.

Key arguments advanced across the volume include:

  1. The Necessity of Philosophy: Philosophy acts as an "underlabourer" by exposing prejudices and unquestioned assumptions, mapping the field of knowledge, and refining methods. Furthermore, reflective investigation into the social sciences necessitates asking philosophical questions regarding proper methods, objectivity, and the role of values.
  2. Critique of Positivism and Empiricism: The study details the basic doctrines of empiricism (the notion that knowledge comes from experience and that science is the highest form of knowledge). It scrutinizes the positivist commitment to extending the empiricist model of natural science to the study of social life (naturalism), finding this approach inherently problematic due to unresolved difficulties in the empiricist view of science itself.
  3. The Interpretive Traditions: The book examines approaches that prioritize human consciousness and meaning (reflexivity). These range from instrumental rationality (Weber's focus on practical goals), to rationality as rule-following (Winch/Gadamer, emphasizing culture and language games), and critical rationality (Habermas/Critical Theory, viewing rationality as a critical standard for emancipation).
  4. Alternative Approaches: It explores non-positivist approaches that offer new ways to conceptualize science and social reality, including the sociological study of science, Critical Realism (emphasizing an independently existing, stratified reality), Feminist Standpoint Epistemology (linking knowledge claims to social position and gender), and Post-structuralism/Post-modernism (emphasizing discourse, fragmentation, and anti-foundationalism).

Structure and Methodology

The methodology is rooted in philosophical comparison and conceptual analysis, organized around key sub-disciplines: epistemology (theory of knowledge), ontology (theory of what exists), logic, and ethics/moral philosophy.

The book’s structure is notably non-conventional, beginning with three chapters dedicated to the philosophy of natural science and the critics of empiricism before moving into social science proper.

The volume proceeds systematically through various traditions, primarily divided into:

  • Part I (Chapters 2–4): Empiricism, Positivism, and Alternatives to Empiricism.
  • Part II (Chapters 5–7): Interpretive Approaches (Instrumental, Rule-Following, Critical Rationality).
  • Part III (Chapters 8–10): Recent Developments (Critical Realism, Feminism, Post-structuralism).

The division of labor saw Ted Benton primarily responsible for chapters dealing with empiricism, natural science, critical realism, and feminism (Chs. 2, 3, 4, 8, and 9), while Ian Craib focused on interpretive approaches and post-structuralism (Chs. 5, 6, 7, and 10). Both contributed to the introduction and conclusion.

For the Second Edition (2011), published after Ian Craib’s death, Ted Benton added post-scripts to relevant chapters and a substantial new Commentary on Recent Developments (Chapter 12). Benton retained Craib's original chapters unchanged, but introduced his own thoughts where they differed from Craib’s, returning the book closer to the authors’ original intention to emphasize debate.

Unique Contributions and Significance

The book's significance lies in its rigorous mapping of complex intellectual terrain and its dedicated focus on methodological questions arising from within the social sciences.

  1. Overcoming Dichotomies: The most significant contribution is the systematic argument that the field is not exhausted by the positivist/interpretivist contrast. By dedicating substantial space to alternatives—especially Critical Realism—the book presents a more nuanced view, suggesting that natural and social sciences share similarities and differences in a sophisticated way.
  2. Intellectual Honesty and Reflexivity: The authors explicitly connect philosophical positions to their own "personal intellectual (and political) journeys," discussing their initial commitments to Marxism, and how subsequent movements (black power, gay rights, feminism, the green movement) forced them to deeply revise basic assumptions. This provides an insightful model of scholarly self-reflection for students.
  3. The Defense of Philosophy: The book ultimately acts "In Defence of Philosophy," arguing that engaging in philosophical argument is intrinsically valuable, helping to counter the increasing dominance of purely instrumental thinking. Craib’s focus on subjectivity and the "imponderable area of creativity" within individuals provides a deep critique against reductive simplifications.

Evaluation of Strengths and Weaknesses

The strength of the work is its comprehensiveness and commitment to fairness. It serves effectively as a high-altitude photograph or map of theoretical approaches, suitable for situating various social science disciplines. The pedagogical approach encourages students to participate in arguments and challenge their own positions.

A perceived weakness of the first edition, as noted by a reviewer (Garry Potter 2002), was that the authors were perhaps "too scrupulous in being fair to the various positions," leading to a conventional textbook format rather than emphasizing their own provisional intellectual stances. Ted Benton addressed this in the second edition by making his sympathies more evident in the new commentary, acknowledging the desire for a more "committed" character.

Another challenge noted by Benton is the difficulty of achieving "completeness" in covering the exploding volume of academic literature.

Comparison with Other Related Works

The book positions itself in relation to traditional philosophical models, contrasting the "masterbuilder" view (metaphysics/rationalism) with the "underlabourer" view (empiricism). It is also explicitly presented as a companion to the Themes in Social Theory series.

The comparison of foundational social theorists is integral:

  • Positivism vs. Interpretivism: The study systematically contrasts the empiricist, quantitative focus of positivism (exemplified by Durkheim, but not exclusively), with interpretive theories like those of Weber, which focus on subjective meaning (verstehen) and instrumental rationality.
  • Marxism/Critical Theory: Critical Rationality (Habermas) is presented as a continuation of the emancipatory project of the Enlightenment, arguing that reason provides a means to judge and critique different forms of life. This tradition offers a theory of ideology, wherein systematic mistakes in understanding the world are rooted in social structure, differentiating it from purely hermeneutic approaches.
  • Critical Realism (CR): CR is highlighted as an approach that attempts to combine hermeneutic and structuralist insights. It distinguishes itself by claiming that the social world is "variegated" and stratified, made up of different levels of being, suggesting that "what we see is less than what there is". CR provides a "more sophisticated view" than earlier approaches regarding the similarities and differences between social and natural science.

Key Insights and Takeaways

For researchers, students, and practitioners, the book offers several key takeaways:

  • The Problem of Transparency: Social life is not always transparent; philosophical grounding is needed to understand phenomena that actors struggle to grasp. Social scientific concepts must overcome "misleading appearances".
  • The Interplay of Causal and Meaning Adequacy: In interpretive work, explanations must meet the criteria of meaning adequacy (being a credible, rational story) and causal adequacy (identifying contributing factors through comparative examination).
  • The Inescapability of Values: Values are intrinsically involved in science, even if objectivity is pursued. The debate is not whether values exist, but which values are necessary and supportive of objective knowledge.
  • The Importance of Ontology: Researchers are encouraged to reflect on "what kinds of things are there in the world", as the potential for social science to be "scientific" depends fundamentally on what "society" is assumed to be.
  • Philosophy as Emancipation: The struggle to understand the world and our connectedness to it is intrinsically valuable for human freedom.

Overall Impact and Relevance

Philosophy of Social Science remains highly relevant by providing a necessary philosophical toolkit for confronting the deep disagreements and special difficulties found within the social sciences. The book’s impact is measured by its success as an influential textbook and its ability to sustain critical debate.

The continued relevance of the work is underscored by the material added in the second edition, which demonstrates the ongoing vitality of the issues discussed. Benton’s later commentary engages critically with subsequent literature, including the strong defense of Peter Winch, new work on post-Marxist discourse theory, and the proliferation of work in the Critical Realist tradition. The book successfully equips readers to appreciate the complexity, subtlety, and paradoxes of the ideas that inform the study of the social world.