The following is a detailed and analytical review of Philosophy of Social Science (Second Edition) by Ted Benton and Ian Craib.
Book Review:
Philosophy of Social Science (Second Edition)
Authors: Ted Benton and
Ian Craib
Main Themes,
Arguments, and Author’s Purpose
Philosophy of Social Science (Second Edition) serves primarily as a concise introduction and
"language primer" to the philosophical traditions and contentious
arguments surrounding the study of human social life. The central purpose of
the work is to encourage students of social science to engage in reflexive
inquiry by addressing the fundamental question: "What are we doing when
we attempt to study human social life in a systematic way?". The
authors, drawing on a long history of intellectual collaboration and debate,
present a complex, nuanced picture of the social sciences, arguing that
philosophical questions are not externally imposed but arise intrinsically from
the "special difficulties and deep disagreements" found within the
disciplines themselves.
The main arguments revolve around charting the
philosophical terrain (epistemology, ontology, logic, ethics) and navigating
the perennial tension between naturalistic (positivist) approaches that
model social science on natural science, and anti-naturalistic
(interpretivist) approaches that emphasize meaning, culture, and
subjectivity.
Crucially, the book argues against a simple
dichotomy, dedicating significant space to developing and defending
alternative, post-empiricist models of science, notably Critical Realism,
which seeks to overcome the sterile opposition between meaning and cause, or
particular versus universal methods. The authors frame their endeavor as
"underlabouring" for the social sciences—providing clarity,
criticizing prejudices, mapping existing knowledge, and refining methods.
Chapter-by-Chapter
Breakdown
The book is structured to move logically from
traditional philosophical debates concerning natural science toward
contemporary debates specifically within social theory, before returning to a
synthesis in the context of critical realism and critique.
Part I: The
Natural Science Model and Its Critics (Chapters 1–4)
- Chapter 1 (Introduction): Establishes the necessity of philosophy,
detailing the "masterbuilder" versus "underlabourer"
views. It introduces the "philosophical toolkit": Epistemology
(the theory of knowledge, contrasting rationalism and empiricism), Ontology
(the theory of what exists, contrasting materialism and idealism), Logic,
and Ethics/Moral Philosophy.
- Chapter 2 (Empiricism and Positivism in
Science): Outlines
the empiricist account of knowledge through seven basic doctrines,
emphasizing testability, the reliance on observation/experiment, and the 'covering
law' model of explanation. Positivism is characterized by extending
these methods to the study of social life (naturalism) and the notion of
"social engineering". A strength of this chapter is its clear
demarcation of key concepts, but it highlights the inherent difficulty in
drawing a clear dividing line between science and 'pseudo-science' using
strict testability criteria.
- Chapter 3 (Some Problems of Empiricism and
Positivism): This
chapter provides extensive critiques of empiricism, highlighting that
observations are conceptually mediated ("theory dependence of
observation"). It tackles the problem of induction and notes the
distinction between confirmation and Popper’s falsification. It
discusses incommensurability (rival theories talking past each
other). A key strength is the introduction of different roles for theory:
functional, historical-narrative, and the hypothetico-deductive model,
which challenges the empiricist "flat ontology" by suggesting
reality is layered.
- Chapter 4 (Science, Nature and Society: Some
Alternatives to Empiricism): Reviews
post-empiricist alternatives, emphasizing the social and historical
location of science. Key ideas include the Frankfurt School's critique
(science as domination), Merton’s institutional imperatives for
science, the French tradition of Historical Epistemology
(epistemological breaks), Kuhn’s concept of the paradigm and
scientific revolutions, and the Strong Programme (impartiality and
symmetry). A weakness is noted in the early formulation of Actor-Network
Theory, which tended toward cynicism and rejected reason itself.
Part II:
Interpretive Approaches (Chapters 5–7)
These chapters explore the arguments that social
sciences must adopt distinct methods due to the nature of their objects
(self-conscious, reflexive human beings).
- Chapter 5 (Interpretive Approaches 1:
Instrumental Rationality): Focuses on
instrumental rationality (action directed towards practical, achievable
ends). The pivotal thinker is Max Weber, who defined the object of
sociology as "meaningful, rational, social action" and used ideal
types and verstehen (interpretive understanding). Weber's
criteria for judgment are meaning adequacy and causal adequacy
(through comparative analysis). Related approaches include Phenomenology
(Schutz’s typifications/second-order typifications), and Rational
Choice Theory (maximizing profit/benefits). The strength lies in
establishing the hermeneutic starting point, although the chapter notes
the inherent difficulty in equating reasons with causes.
- Chapter 6 (Interpretive Approaches 2:
Rationality as Rule-Following): Moves
beyond individual meaning to collective culture. Peter Winch's influential
argument, rooted in Wittgenstein, states that concepts settle the form of
experience and that social life is rule-following. Since rules can
be followed wrongly or rightly, social action cannot be understood through
causal explanations. The chapter explores the resulting relativism
and introduces Alisdair MacIntyre’s emphasis on morality rooted in tradition
and human life understood through narratives. Finally, Gadamer’s
Hermeneutics stresses the historical nature of understanding and the hermeneutic
circle (part-to-whole movement). A weakness is Gadamer’s potential
conservatism and overemphasis on the authority of tradition, which hinders
the critique of ideologies.
- Chapter 7 (Interpretive Approaches 3: Critical
Rationality): Focuses on
critique and emancipation. It introduces the Dialectic (Hegel/Marx)
and the Frankfurt School's concept of Ideology (systematically
distorted ideas, resulting in "second nature"). Habermas
attempts a synthesis, organizing social scientific approaches around three
cognitive interests (technical, practical, emancipatory).
Habermas's model—which posits the ideal speech situation and communicative
rationality as democratic standards—offers a strong alternative to
relativism.
Part III: New
Directions (Chapters 8–10) and Conclusion
- Chapter 8 (Critical Realism and the Social
Sciences): Presents
Critical Realism (CR) as a non-positivist, yet realist alternative. CR
asserts that reality is stratified (real/mechanisms, actual/events,
empirical/observations) and differentiates between the intransitive
dimension (independent reality) and the transitive dimension
(conceptual, social process of knowledge production). It advocates a critical
naturalism for social science. Crucially, it proposes the transformational
model of social action to resolve the structure/agency problem, and
argues that knowledge can support emancipation through explanatory
critique (identifying social structures that cause suffering or false
beliefs).
- Chapter 9 (Feminism, Knowledge and Society): Examines the challenges posed by feminism to
traditional epistemology, especially regarding objectivity and
universality. It contrasts Feminist Empiricism with Feminist
Standpoint Epistemology (S. Harding, H. Rose, N. Hartsock), which
argues that marginalized social positions yield more adequate knowledge (a
critique of "malestream" science). The chapter notes the
internal feminist critique from Post-modern Feminism, which rejects
the universal category "woman" and epistemology itself.
- Chapter 10 (Post-structuralism and
Post-modernism): Examines
the shift from structuralism (underlying structures, linguistic analogy)
to Post-structuralism (Foucault's discourse/power-knowledge and
Derrida's deconstruction/logocentrism). Post-modernism (Lyotard)
denies the possibility of meta-narratives, emphasizing
fragmentation, plurality, and skepticism toward foundational truths. The
critical reflection here acknowledges the 'posts' intellectual provocation
but argues that the abandonment of reason is self-refuting, as critique
must employ the Enlightenment principles it denies.
- Chapter 11 (Conclusion: In Defence of
Philosophy):
Re-emphasizes the complexity of the social world, advocating for
intellectual life beyond simple instrumental thinking. It argues that
philosophical reflection on scientific practice justifies key
distinctions, such as critical realism’s transitive/intransitive
dimensions, and asserts that social structures exist independently of our
concepts.
- Chapter 12 (Commentary on Recent Developments): Added by Benton for the Second Edition (Ian
Craib having died in 2002). This chapter provides explicit critical
commentary, particularly focusing on the debate surrounding Peter Winch's
anti-scientism and discussing the development of post-Marxist discourse
theory (Glynos and Howarth). It highlights the proliferation of work
in the critical realist tradition since the first edition, including
debates on methodology, the structure/agency problem, and Bhaskar's
"spiritual turn".
Historical and
Intellectual Context
The book is deeply rooted in the intellectual
ferment following the Enlightenment, dealing directly with the legacies
of Rationalism and Empiricism. The authors’ intellectual biographies place them
in the generation of the "sixties," sharing an initial strong
political and moral commitment, particularly to Marxism. This background
meant they were concerned throughout their careers with adapting social theory
to the massive intellectual and political challenges presented by movements
such as feminism, environmentalism, and anti-racism. The philosophical
differences between the authors—Ian Craib’s focus on subjectivity,
psychoanalysis, and anti-naturalism, and Ted Benton’s commitment to naturalism,
critical realism, and life sciences—structured the book’s division of labor and
its pervasive internal debate.
The book’s structure reflects the movement in
philosophy of social science away from the mid-20th-century dominance of
logical positivism and the rise of alternatives like post-Kuhnian philosophy of
science, which emphasizes the social practice of science.
Relevance Today: The relevance of
the book remains high because it addresses persistent issues: the tension
between scientific explanation and human meaning, the role of values in
objective research, and the possibility of rational critique in a relativistic
world. Chapter 12 ensures contemporary relevance by engaging with recent
developments in critical realism and post-structuralism/post-Marxism, showing
how these theoretical traditions continue to evolve and clash.
Evaluation of
Author’s Style, Clarity, and Use of Evidence
The authors successfully achieve the tone of a
comprehensive "primer" and "map" of the field. The writing
maintains a "careful and respectful attitude to alternative points of
view". Ian Craib’s contributions are lauded for their ability to
communicate complex and difficult ideas in a direct and accessible way,
capturing the "sense of excitement and bewilderment" of intellectual
exploration.
The use of evidence is primarily conceptual
and historical. The authors meticulously reconstruct the intellectual
journeys that led to key philosophical stances (e.g., tracing Kantian ideas to
Weberian methodology, or Lukácsian ideas to feminist standpoint theory). They
employ transcendental arguments (Bhaskar) as evidence for ontological
claims about reality. They use concrete examples—like Darwin’s natural
selection, the ambiguity of visual perception, or the Azande witchcraft
debate—to make abstract philosophical points clear. The critical reflection
notes that the book "depends on a real philosophical argument" rather
than empirical investigation of any single discipline, enhancing its role as a
work of philosophy.
Comparison with
Other Works
The book positions itself as a companion to
foundational theoretical texts and introduces multiple traditions concisely. By
systematically reviewing and critiquing Empiricism (Popper, Ayer) and
Positivism (Comte, Durkheim), before diving into interpretive traditions
(Weber, Winch, Gadamer, Habermas), the book covers the territory expected of a
philosophy of social science text.
However, its strength lies in moving beyond the
traditional positivism/hermeneutics binary by promoting post-empiricist,
non-reductive approaches, specifically Critical Realism. In doing so, it
engages with contemporary social theory (e.g., Giddens's structuration theory,
which is discussed as a different approach to the structure/agency problem than
the critical realist transformational model). It explicitly compares its mission
to the foundational philosophical work of thinkers like Gramsci.
Critical
Reflection and Target Audience
The greatest contribution of Philosophy of Social
Science is its rigorous argument for sustained philosophical reflection
within the social sciences, demonstrating that the deepest methodological
disputes stem from fundamental disagreements over epistemology and ontology. It
contributes significantly by showing that natural science itself is not
monolithic, allowing for the possibility of a "scientific" social
study that rejects the narrow, surface-level focus of traditional positivism.
The book's refusal to offer settled conclusions,
instead inviting the reader to participate in the debate—to "argue against
yourself from alternative points of view"—is a key strength. It makes the
powerful case that intellectual life and the struggle for understanding are
themselves inherently valuable and emancipatory.
Target Readers and Researchers: The book is ideal for students and apprentices
to the social sciences. It specifically benefits those seeking a framework
to:
- Situate their discipline within wider philosophical traditions (e.g.,
sociology, economics, history, psychology).
- Understand the philosophical foundations of competing theoretical approaches, such as
rational choice theory, feminism, or post-structuralism.
- Engage in advanced research by clarifying methodological presuppositions,
particularly those seeking to integrate meaning/interpretation with
causal/structural explanation (e.g., researchers interested in Critical
Realism, critical theory, or issues of power and ideology).
- Reflect critically on the moral and political
implications of their
work, moving beyond simple factual investigation to normative evaluation.
No comments:
Post a Comment